苹果补充什么维生素| 震慑是什么意思| 毛主席什么时候死的| 脚气是什么样的| 第一次查怀孕挂什么科| 次抛是什么意思| 黑色的鸟是什么鸟| 肠道菌群失调有什么症状| 急性结肠炎什么症状| 验血能查出什么| 做宫腔镜检查需要提前做什么准备| blacklabel是什么牌子| bl和bg是什么意思| vivo是什么牌子| 肾低密度灶是什么意思| rd是什么| 网线长什么样| 白蛋白是什么| 接见是什么意思| 腱鞘炎是什么引起的| jbp什么意思| 缓刑是什么| 腿纹不对称有什么影响| 拔了智齿需要注意什么| 干眼症有什么症状| 药物流产后需要注意什么| 糖精对人体有什么危害| 不感冒什么意思| 肠系膜淋巴结肿大吃什么药| 为什么韩国叫棒子国| 惊蛰吃什么| 胎盘血池是什么意思| 吃了布洛芬不能吃什么| 李子有什么营养| 苦丁茶有什么作用和功效| 牛的四个胃分别叫什么| 疤痕憩室什么意思| 非洲人一日三餐吃什么| 天什么地| 卵巢多囊是什么意思| 尿酸高的人吃什么食物好| 什么叫八字| 高烧拉肚子是什么原因| 奇异果是什么| 嗜酸性粒细胞偏高是什么原因| 鳄鱼吃什么食物| 昙花什么时候开花| 大腿根疼是什么原因| 19岁属什么生肖| 小便多是什么原因男性| 必迈跑鞋什么档次| 胆囊结石用什么药好| 迅雷不及掩耳之势是什么意思| 老炮儿是什么意思啊| 眉头长痘痘什么原因| 胡萝卜和什么不能一起吃| 胰腺炎为什么血糖高| 为什么不建议吃大豆油| 劣迹斑斑是什么意思| 什么发什么强| 吃什么降血糖最快| 家有小女是什么生肖| 九月十二号是什么星座| 疼痛科属于什么科| 前门大街有什么好玩的| 吃什么改善睡眠| 清炖羊肉放什么调料| 入职是什么意思| 结扎挂什么科| 什么东西越晒越湿| rv是什么意思| 腱鞘囊肿是什么原因引起的| 检查尿常规挂什么科| 女人为什么比男人长寿| 性格内向的人适合做什么工作| 小便失禁是什么原因男性| 什么东西补肾最好| 割包皮有什么影响| 糖尿病能吃什么水果| 发热门诊属于什么科| 女人严重口臭挂什么科| 其他垃圾有什么| 内向的人适合做什么工作| 草字头有什么字| 并蒂是什么意思| 什么人容易长智齿| 什么湖什么海| 爱意是什么意思| 6月7日什么星座| 为什么夏天越来越热| 附件炎吃什么药效果好| 茅台酒为什么这么贵| 甘油三酯高吃什么食物降得快| 孔雀开屏寓意什么意思| slogan什么意思| 喝栀子茶有什么好处| 什么时候敷面膜是最佳时间| 提辖相当于现在什么官| 广西有什么特产| 第一次需要注意什么| 心重是什么意思| 父亲节送爸爸什么| 阴道瘙痒用什么药| 白介素2是治疗什么病的| 吃brunch是什么意思啊| 百什么争鸣成语| 神经衰弱吃什么药好| 吃什么排出全身毒素| kiko是什么意思| 品规是什么意思| 什么狗不掉毛适合家养| 婴儿黄疸母亲忌口什么| 翎字五行属什么| 打卤面都有什么卤| 泰坦尼克号什么时候上映的| 鹦鹉喜欢吃什么东西| 龟头炎什么症状| 幽门杆菌有什么症状| 甘草片不能和什么药一起吃| 小猫不能吃什么| 什么是护理学| 桥本氏甲状腺炎吃什么药| 慷他人之慨什么意思| 暗忖是什么意思| 喝苹果醋有什么好处| 心慌是什么原因引起的| 1993年出生属什么生肖| 经常生闷气会得什么病| 万花筒是什么| 杨梅有什么功效与作用| 四平八稳是什么意思| 喜欢绿色的女人是什么性格| 人为什么会得肿瘤| 天枢是什么意思| 为什么吃了饭就想睡觉| 泌尿系感染吃什么药| 婴儿放屁臭是什么原因| 消渴病是什么病| 什么叫全科医生| 什么是佝偻病有什么症状| 胃酸是什么原因| 六月二十四是什么日子| 为什么叫汉族| 肩膀骨头响是什么原因| 公开遴选公务员是什么意思| 八拜之交是什么生肖| owl是什么意思| 船舷是什么意思| 胰腺在人体起什么作用| 大陆人去香港需要什么证件| 什么是雾霾| 二聚体是什么意思| 公分是什么单位| 做梦梦到搬家什么意思| 酒糟鼻买什么药膏去红| 胃病吃什么好| 挫是什么意思| 腰间盘突出压迫神经什么症状| 711是什么星座| 乔治白属于什么档次| 口嗨是什么意思| 右手无名指戴戒指什么意思| 颈动脉b超是检查什么| 尿液结晶是什么意思| 乳腺发炎吃什么消炎药| 1月20日什么星座| miu是什么意思| 胆红素是什么意思| 智齿长什么样| 阴茎溃疡用什么药| 九五至尊是什么生肖| 睡觉老做梦是什么原因| 房性心动过速是什么意思| 芒果与什么食物相克| 狗狗肠胃炎吃什么药| ed是什么意思| 性激素六项什么时候查| 狗吃什么药会立马就死| 黄芪什么味道| 科目二学什么| 尿酸高适合吃什么菜| 白领是什么意思| 梦见吃药是什么意思| 劲酒加什么好喝| 拉大便有血是什么原因| 腰椎间盘膨出是什么意思| 吐血是什么病| 丙氨酸氨基转移酶高吃什么药| 人格独立是什么意思| 低血糖吃什么水果| 邹字五行属什么| 什么是梅毒| 发蜡和发泥有什么区别| 生目念什么| 拔罐红色是什么原因| 党参长什么样| 日本古代叫什么| 快闪店是什么意思| 互诉衷肠是什么意思| rh血型阴性是什么意思| 肝脏b超能检查出什么| 头脑简单是什么生肖| 谷草转氨酶偏低是什么原因| 乳腺囊肿和乳腺结节有什么区别| 牙龈肿了吃什么药| 梦见看房子是什么预兆| 十二年是什么婚| 伪娘是什么意思| 职业暴露是什么意思| 亚麻色是什么颜色| 梦见桥断了是什么意思| 身体缺钾是什么原因造成的| 男人尿道炎吃什么药最好| 尿痛是什么原因| 遗精是什么意思啊| 今天开什么奖| 申酉是什么时间| 津津有味什么意思| 肺心病吃什么药| 脖子长痘痘是什么原因| 米杏色是什么颜色| 智齿拔了有什么影响| 璨字五行属什么| 百无一用是什么意思| 吃什么化痰| 宫颈液基细胞学检查是什么| 吃什么食物能降低胆固醇| 猪润是什么| 嗜睡是什么症状| 小孩鼻子出血什么原因| r级是什么意思| 7月15是什么星座的| 小舅子是什么意思| 宫腔粘连是什么意思| 清华什么专业最好| 小鼠吃什么| 梦见建房子是什么预兆| 白起为什么被赐死| 一什么图画| 桂鱼吃什么食物| 计抛是什么意思| 兔子吃什么| 辅酶q10什么时间吃最好| 早上口干口苦是什么原因| 生肖龙和什么生肖相冲| 嘴巴苦苦的是什么原因| 红花油和活络油有什么区别| 狐假虎威什么意思| 脾胃气虚吃什么中成药| 理气是什么意思| 姨妈期可以做什么运动| 什么的银发| 辅酶是什么| 宫颈糜烂用什么药好得快| 复方氨酚苯海拉明片是什么药| 竹棉和纯棉有什么区别| 蛋白粉什么时候吃| 卧推80公斤什么水平| 为什么一直睡不着| 孕妇吃什么容易滑胎| 漂亮的近义词是什么| 鸡蛋干配什么菜炒好吃| 什么的枝干| 二尖瓣反流吃什么药| 百度

沈阳市群团组织“擦亮沈阳”

百度   该支出法案将在2018财年为NASA额外提供亿美元用于建造可为太空发射系统火箭(SLS)所用的新发射台。

A thought experiment is an imaginary scenario that is meant to elucidate or test an argument or theory. It is often an experiment that would be hard, impossible, or unethical to actually perform. It can also be an abstract hypothetical that is meant to test our intuitions about morality or other fundamental philosophical questions.[2][3][4][5][6]

Schr?dinger's cat (1935) presents a cat that is in a superposition of alive and dead states, depending on a random quantum event. It illustrates the counter-intuitive implications of Bohr's Copenhagen interpretation when applied to everyday objects.[1]

History

edit

The ancient Greek δε?κνυμι, deiknymi, 'thought experiment', "was the most ancient pattern of mathematical proof", and existed before Euclidean mathematics,[7] where the emphasis was on the conceptual, rather than on the experimental part of a thought experiment.

Johann Witt-Hansen established that Hans Christian ?rsted was the first to use the equivalent German term Gedankenexperiment c.?1812.[8][9] ?rsted was also the first to use the equivalent term Gedankenversuch in 1820.

By 1883, Ernst Mach used Gedankenexperiment in a different sense, to denote exclusively the imaginary conduct of a real experiment that would be subsequently performed as a real physical experiment by his students.[10] Physical and mental experimentation could then be contrasted: Mach asked his students to provide him with explanations whenever the results from their subsequent, real, physical experiment differed from those of their prior, imaginary experiment.

The English term thought experiment was coined as a calque of Gedankenexperiment, and it first appeared in the 1897 English translation of one of Mach's papers.[11] Prior to its emergence, the activity of posing hypothetical questions that employed subjunctive reasoning had existed for a very long time for both scientists and philosophers. The irrealis moods are ways to categorize it or to speak about it. This helps explain the extremely wide and diverse range of the application of the term thought experiment once it had been introduced into English.

 
Galileo's thought experiment concerned the outcome (c) of attaching a small stone (a) to a larger one (b).

Galileo's demonstration that falling objects must fall at the same rate regardless of their masses was a significant step forward in the history of modern science. This is widely thought[12] to have been a straightforward physical demonstration, involving climbing up the Leaning Tower of Pisa and dropping two heavy weights off it, whereas in fact, it was a logical demonstration, using the thought experiment technique. The experiment is described by Galileo in his 1638 work Two New Sciences thus:

Salviati: If then we take two bodies whose natural speeds are different, it is clear that on uniting the two, the more rapid one will be partly retarded by the slower, and the slower will be somewhat hastened by the swifter. Do you not agree with me in this opinion?
Simplicio: You are unquestionably right.
Salviati: But if this is true, and if a large stone moves with a speed of, say, eight while a smaller moves with a speed of four, then when they are united, the system will move with a speed less than eight; but the two stones when tied together make a stone larger than that which before moved with a speed of eight. Hence the heavier body moves with less speed than the lighter; an effect which is contrary to your supposition. Thus you see how, from your assumption that the heavier body moves more rapidly than the lighter one, I infer that the heavier body moves more slowly.[13]

Uses

edit

Thought experiments may be used to explore a hypothesis and the implementation of theories around it. They are also used in education, or for personal entertainment.[9]

Examples of thought experiments include Schr?dinger's cat, that was meant to attack the Copenhagen Interpretation of quantum mechanics by showing that its assumptions could lead to the seemingly absurd condition of a cat being simultaneously alive and dead, and Maxwell's demon, which attempts to demonstrate the ability of a hypothetical finite being to violate the 2nd law of thermodynamics.

It is a common element of science-fiction stories.[14]

Thought experiments, which are well-structured, well-defined hypothetical questions that employ subjunctive reasoning (irrealis moods) – "What might happen (or, what might have happened) if . . . " – have been used to pose questions in philosophy at least since Greek antiquity, some pre-dating Socrates.[15] In physics and other sciences many thought experiments date from the 19th and especially the 20th Century, but examples can be found at least as early as Galileo.

In thought experiments, we gain new information by rearranging or reorganizing empirical data in a new way and drawing new inferences from them, or by looking at these data from a different and unusual perspective. In Galileo's thought experiment, for example, the rearrangement of empirical experience consists of the original idea of combining bodies of different weights.[16]

Thought experiments have been used in philosophy (especially ethics), physics, and other fields (such as cognitive psychology, history, political science, economics, social psychology, law, organizational studies, marketing, and epidemiology). In law, the synonym "hypothetical" is frequently used for such experiments.

Regardless of their intended goal, all thought experiments display a patterned way of thinking that is designed to allow us to explain, predict, and control events in a better and more productive way.

Theoretical consequences

edit

In terms of their theoretical consequences, thought experiments generally:

  • challenge (or even refute) a prevailing theory, often involving the device known as reductio ad absurdum, (as in Galileo's original argument, a proof by contradiction),
  • confirm a prevailing theory,
  • establish a new theory, or
  • simultaneously refute a prevailing theory and establish a new theory through a process of mutual exclusion

Practical applications

edit

Thought experiments can produce some very important and different outlooks on previously unknown or unaccepted theories. However, they may make those theories themselves irrelevant, and could possibly create new problems that are just as difficult, or possibly more difficult to resolve.

In terms of their practical application, thought experiments are generally created to:

  • challenge the prevailing status quo (which includes activities such as correcting misinformation (or misapprehension), identify flaws in the argument(s) presented, to preserve (for the long-term) objectively established fact, and to refute specific assertions that some particular thing is permissible, forbidden, known, believed, possible, or necessary)
  • extrapolate beyond (or interpolate within) the boundaries of already established fact
  • predict and forecast the (otherwise) indefinite and unknowable future
  • explain the past
  • facilitate the retrodiction, postdiction and hindcasting of the otherwise indefinite and unknowable past
  • facilitate decision making, choice, and strategy selection
  • solve problems, and generate ideas;
  • move current unsolved problems into another more productive problem space (e.g. functional fixedness)
  • attribute causation, preventability, blame, and responsibility for specific outcomes
  • assess culpability and compensatory damages in social and legal contexts
  • ensure the repeat of past success
  • examine the extent to which past events might have occurred differently
  • ensure the future avoidance of past failures

Types

edit
 
Temporal representation of a prefactual thought experiment[17]

Seven types of thought experiment, in which one reasons from causes to effects or effects to causes, can be identified:[18][19]

Prefactual

edit

Prefactual (before the fact) thought experiments – the term prefactual was coined by Lawrence J. Sanna in 1998[20] – speculate on possible future outcomes, given the present, and ask "What will be the outcome if event E occurs?".[21][22]

Counterfactual

edit
 
Temporal representation of a counterfactual thought experiment[23]

Counterfactual (contrary to established fact) thought experiments – the term counterfactual was coined by Nelson Goodman in 1947,[24] extending Roderick Chisholm's (1946) notion of a "contrary-to-fact conditional"[25] – speculate on the possible outcomes of a different past;[26] and ask "What might have happened if A had happened instead of B?" (e.g., "If Isaac Newton and Gottfried Leibniz had cooperated with each other, what would mathematics look like today?").[27][28][22]

The study of counterfactual speculation has increasingly engaged the interest of scholars in a wide range of domains such as philosophy,[29] psychology,[30] cognitive psychology,[31] history,[32] political science,[33] economics,[34] social psychology,[35] law,[36] organizational theory,[37] marketing,[38] and epidemiology.[39]

Semifactual

edit
 
Temporal representation of a semifactual thought experiment[23]

Semifactual thought experiments – the term semifactual was coined by Nelson Goodman in 1947[24][40] – speculate on the extent to which things might have remained the same, despite there being a different past; and asks the question Even though X happened instead of E, would Y have still occurred? (e.g., Even if the goalie had moved left, rather than right, could he have intercepted a ball that was traveling at such a speed?).[41][22]

Semifactual speculations are an important part of clinical medicine.

Predictive

edit
 
Temporal representation of prediction, forecasting and nowcasting[42]

The activity of prediction attempts to project the circumstances of the present into the future.[43][44] According to David Sarewitz and Roger Pielke (1999, p123), scientific prediction takes two forms:

  1. "The elucidation of invariant – and therefore predictive – principles of nature"; and
  2. "[Using] suites of observational data and sophisticated numerical models in an effort to foretell the behavior or evolution of complex phenomena".[45]

Although they perform different social and scientific functions, the only difference between the qualitatively identical activities of predicting, forecasting, and nowcasting is the distance of the speculated future from the present moment occupied by the user.[46] Whilst the activity of nowcasting, defined as "a detailed description of the current weather along with forecasts obtained by extrapolation up to 2 hours ahead", is essentially concerned with describing the current state of affairs, it is common practice to extend the term "to cover very-short-range forecasting up to 12 hours ahead" (Browning, 1982, p.ix).[47][48]

Hindcasting

edit
 
Temporal representation of hindcasting[42]

The activity of hindcasting involves running a forecast model after an event has happened in order to test whether the model's simulation is valid.[43][44]

Retrodiction

edit
 
Temporal representation of retrodiction or postdiction[49]

The activity of retrodiction (or postdiction) involves moving backward in time, step-by-step, in as many stages as are considered necessary, from the present into the speculated past to establish the ultimate cause of a specific event (e.g., reverse engineering and forensics).[50][44]

Given that retrodiction is a process in which "past observations, events, add and data are used as evidence to infer the process(es) that produced them" and that diagnosis "involve[s] going from visible effects such as symptoms, signs and the like to their prior causes",[51] the essential balance between prediction and retrodiction could be characterized as:

retrodiction : diagnosis :: prediction : prognosis

regardless of whether the prognosis is of the course of the disease in the absence of treatment, or of the application of a specific treatment regimen to a specific disorder in a particular patient.[52]

Backcasting

edit
 
Temporal representation of backcasting[53]

The activity of backcasting – the term backcasting was coined by John Robinson in 1982[54] – involves establishing the description of a very definite and very specific future situation. It then involves an imaginary moving backward in time, step-by-step, in as many stages as are considered necessary, from the future to the present to reveal the mechanism through which that particular specified future could be attained from the present.[55][56][57]

Backcasting is not concerned with predicting the future:

The major distinguishing characteristic of backcasting analyses is the concern, not with likely energy futures, but with how desirable futures can be attained. It is thus explicitly normative, involving 'working backward' from a particular future end-point to the present to determine what policy measures would be required to reach that future.[58]

According to Jansen (1994, p. 503:[59]

Within the framework of technological development, "forecasting" concerns the extrapolation of developments towards the future and the exploration of achievements that can be realized through technology in the long term. Conversely, the reasoning behind "backcasting" is: on the basis of an interconnecting picture of demands technology must meet in the future – "sustainability criteria" – to direct and determine the process that technology development must take and possibly also the pace at which this development process must take effect. Backcasting [is] both an important aid in determining the direction technology development must take and in specifying the targets to be set for this purpose. As such, backcasting is an ideal search toward determining the nature and scope of the technological challenge posed by sustainable development, and it can thus serve to direct the search process toward new – sustainable – technology.

Fields

edit

Thought experiments have been used in a variety of fields, including philosophy, law, physics, and mathematics. In philosophy they have been used at least since classical antiquity, some pre-dating Socrates. In law, they were well known to Roman lawyers quoted in the Digest.[60] In physics and other sciences, notable thought experiments date from the 19th and, especially, the 20th century; but examples can be found at least as early as Galileo.

Philosophy

edit

In philosophy, a thought experiment typically presents an imagined scenario with the intention of eliciting an intuitive or reasoned response about the way things are in the thought experiment. (Philosophers might also supplement their thought experiments with theoretical reasoning designed to support the desired intuitive response.) The scenario will typically be designed to target a particular philosophical notion, such as morality, or the nature of the mind or linguistic reference. The response to the imagined scenario is supposed to tell us about the nature of that notion in any scenario, real or imagined.

For example, a thought experiment might present a situation in which an agent intentionally kills an innocent for the benefit of others. Here, the relevant question is not whether the action is moral or not, but more broadly whether a moral theory is correct that says morality is determined solely by an action's consequences (See Consequentialism). John Searle imagines a man in a locked room who receives written sentences in Chinese, and returns written sentences in Chinese, according to a sophisticated instruction manual. Here, the relevant question is not whether or not the man understands Chinese, but more broadly, whether a functionalist theory of mind is correct.

It is generally hoped that there is universal agreement about the intuitions that a thought experiment elicits. (Hence, in assessing their own thought experiments, philosophers may appeal to "what we should say," or some such locution.) A successful thought experiment will be one in which intuitions about it are widely shared. But often, philosophers differ in their intuitions about the scenario.

Other philosophical uses of imagined scenarios arguably are thought experiments also. In one use of scenarios, philosophers might imagine persons in a particular situation (maybe ourselves), and ask what they would do.

For example, in the veil of ignorance, John Rawls asks us to imagine a group of persons in a situation where they know nothing about themselves, and are charged with devising a social or political organization. The use of the state of nature to imagine the origins of government, as by Thomas Hobbes and John Locke, may also be considered a thought experiment. S?ren Kierkegaard explored the possible ethical and religious implications of Abraham's binding of Isaac in Fear and Trembling. Similarly, Friedrich Nietzsche, in On the Genealogy of Morals, speculated about the historical development of Judeo-Christian morality, with the intent of questioning its legitimacy.

An early written thought experiment was Plato's allegory of the cave.[61] Another historic thought experiment was Avicenna's "Floating Man" thought experiment in the 11th century. He asked his readers to imagine themselves suspended in the air isolated from all sensations in order to demonstrate human self-awareness and self-consciousness, and the substantiality of the soul.[62]

Science

edit

Scientists tend to use thought experiments as imaginary, "proxy" experiments prior to a real, "physical" experiment (Ernst Mach always argued that these gedankenexperiments were "a necessary precondition for physical experiment"). In these cases, the result of the "proxy" experiment will often be so clear that there will be no need to conduct a physical experiment at all.

Scientists also use thought experiments when particular physical experiments are impossible to conduct (Carl Gustav Hempel labeled these sorts of experiment "theoretical experiments-in-imagination"), such as Einstein's thought experiment of chasing a light beam, leading to special relativity. This is a unique use of a scientific thought experiment, in that it was never carried out, but led to a successful theory, proven by other empirical means.

Properties

edit

Further categorization of thought experiments can be attributed to specific properties.

Possibility

edit

In many thought experiments, the scenario would be nomologically possible, or possible according to the laws of nature. John Searle's Chinese room is nomologically possible.

Some thought experiments present scenarios that are not nomologically possible. In his Twin Earth thought experiment, Hilary Putnam asks us to imagine a scenario in which there is a substance with all of the observable properties of water (e.g., taste, color, boiling point), but is chemically different from water. It has been argued that this thought experiment is not nomologically possible, although it may be possible in some other sense, such as metaphysical possibility. It is debatable whether the nomological impossibility of a thought experiment renders intuitions about it moot.

In some cases, the hypothetical scenario might be considered metaphysically impossible, or impossible in any sense at all. David Chalmers says that we can imagine that there are zombies, or persons who are physically identical to us in every way but who lack consciousness. This is supposed to show that physicalism is false. However, some argue that zombies are inconceivable: we can no more imagine a zombie than we can imagine that 1+1=3. Others have claimed that the conceivability of a scenario may not entail its possibility.

Causal reasoning

edit

The first characteristic pattern that thought experiments display is their orientation in time.[63] They are either:

  • Antefactual speculations: experiments that speculate about what might have happened prior to a specific, designated event, or
  • Postfactual speculations: experiments that speculate about what may happen subsequent to (or consequent upon) a specific, designated event.

The second characteristic pattern is their movement in time in relation to "the present moment standpoint" of the individual performing the experiment; namely, in terms of:

  • Their temporal direction: are they past-oriented or future-oriented?
  • Their temporal sense:
    • (a) in the case of past-oriented thought experiments, are they examining the consequences of temporal "movement" from the present to the past, or from the past to the present? or,
    • (b) in the case of future-oriented thought experiments, are they examining the consequences of temporal "movement" from the present to the future, or from the future to the present?

Relation to real experiments

edit

The relation to real experiments can be quite complex, as can be seen again from an example going back to Albert Einstein. In 1935, with two coworkers, he published a paper on a newly created subject called later the EPR effect (EPR paradox). In this paper, starting from certain philosophical assumptions,[64] on the basis of a rigorous analysis of a certain, complicated, but in the meantime assertedly realizable model, he came to the conclusion that quantum mechanics should be described as "incomplete". Niels Bohr asserted a refutation of Einstein's analysis immediately, and his view prevailed.[65][66][67] After some decades, it was asserted that feasible experiments could prove the error of the EPR paper. These experiments tested the Bell inequalities published in 1964 in a purely theoretical paper. The above-mentioned EPR philosophical starting assumptions were considered to be falsified by the empirical fact (e.g. by the optical real experiments of Alain Aspect).

Thus thought experiments belong to a theoretical discipline, usually to theoretical physics, but often to theoretical philosophy. In any case, it must be distinguished from a real experiment, which belongs naturally to the experimental discipline and has "the final decision on true or not true", at least in physics.

Interactivity

edit

Thought experiments can also be interactive where the author invites people into his thought process through providing alternative paths with alternative outcomes within the narrative, or through interaction with a programmed machine, like a computer program.

Thanks to the advent of the Internet, the digital space has lent itself as a new medium for a new kind of thought experiments. The philosophical work of Stefano Gualeni, for example, focuses on the use of virtual worlds to materialize thought experiments and to playfully negotiate philosophical ideas.[68] His arguments were originally presented in his 2015 book Virtual Worlds as Philosophical Tools.[69]

Gualeni's argument is that the history of philosophy has, until recently, merely been the history of written thought, and digital media can complement and enrich the limited and almost exclusively linguistic approach to philosophical thought.[69][68][70] He considers virtual worlds (like those interactively encountered in videogames) to be philosophically viable and advantageous. This is especially the case in thought experiments, when the recipients of a certain philosophical notion or perspective are expected to objectively test and evaluate different possible courses of action, or in cases where they are confronted with interrogatives concerning non-actual or non-human phenomenologies.[69][68][70]

Examples

edit

Humanities

edit

Physics

edit

Philosophy

edit

Mathematics

edit

Biology

edit

Computer science

edit

Economics

edit

See also

edit

Notes

edit

References

edit
  1. ^ a b Bild, Marius; Fadel, Matteo; Yang, Yu; et al. (20 April 2023). "Schr?dinger cat states of a 16-microgram mechanical oscillator". Science. 380 (6642): 274–278. arXiv:2211.00449. Bibcode:2023Sci...380..274B. doi:10.1126/science.adf7553. PMID 37079693.
  2. ^ Miyamoto, Kentaro; Rushworth, Matthew F.S.; Shea, Nicholas (1 May 2023). "Imagining the future self through thought experiments". Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 27 (5): 446–455. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2023.01.005. ISSN 1364-6613. PMID 36801162.
  3. ^ Gendler, Tamar Szabó (1 January 2022). "Thought Experiments Rethought—and Reperceived". Philosophy of Science. 71 (5): 1152–1163. doi:10.1086/425239. ISSN 0031-8248. S2CID 144114290.
  4. ^ Grush, Rick (1 June 2004). "The emulation theory of representation: Motor control, imagery, and perception". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 2 7 (3): 377–396. doi:10.1017/S0140525X04000093. ISSN 0140-525X. PMID 15736871. S2CID 514252.
  5. ^ Aronowitz, S., & Lombrozo, T. (2020). Learning through simulation. Philosophers' Imprint, 20(1), 1-18.
  6. ^ Bourget, David; Chalmers, David J. (25 July 2023). "Philosophers on Philosophy: The 2020 PhilPapers Survey". Philosophers' Imprint. 23 (1). doi:10.3998/phimp.2109. ISSN 1533-628X.
  7. ^ Szábo, árpád. (1958) " 'Deiknymi' als Mathematischer Terminus fur 'Beweisen' ", Maia N.S. 10 pp. 1–26 as cited by Imre Lakatos (1976) in Proofs and Refutations p. 9. (John Worrall and Elie Zahar, eds.) Cambridge University Press ISBN 0-521-21078-X. The English translation of the title of Szábo's article is "'Deiknymi' as a mathematical expression for 'to prove'", as translated by András Máté Máté, András (Fall 2006). "árpád Szabó and Imre Lakatos, or the Relation Between History and Philosophy of Mathematics" (PDF). Perspectives on Science. 14 (3): 282–301 especially pp. 285, 288. doi:10.1162/posc.2006.14.3.282. Archived from the original (PDF) on 25 April 2012.
  8. ^ Witt-Hansen (1976). Although Experiment is a German word, it is derived from Latin. The synonym Versuch has purely Germanic roots.
  9. ^ a b Brown, James Robert; Fehige, Yiftach (30 September 2019) [1996]. "Thought Experiments". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  10. ^ Mach, Ernst (1883), The Science of Mechanics (6th edition, translated by Thomas J. McCormack), LaSalle, Illinois: Open Court, 1960. pp. 32–41, 159–62.
  11. ^ Mach, Ernst (1897), "On Thought Experiments", in Knowledge and Error (translated by Thomas J. McCormack and Paul Foulkes), Dordrecht Holland: Reidel, 1976, pp. 134-47.
  12. ^ Cohen, Martin, "Wittgenstein's Beetle and Other Classic Thought Experiments", Blackwell, (Oxford), 2005, pp. 55–56.
  13. ^ "Galileo on Aristotle and Acceleration". Retrieved 24 May 2008.
  14. ^ "SFE: Thought Experiment". sf-encyclopedia.com. Retrieved 3 December 2022.
  15. ^ Rescher, N. (1991), "Thought Experiment in Pre-Socratic Philosophy", in Horowitz, T.; Massey, G.J. (eds.), Thought Experiments in Science and philosophy, Rowman & Littlefield, (Savage), pp. 31–41.
  16. ^ Brendal, Elke, "Intuition Pumps and the Proper Use of Thought Experiments". Dialectica. V.58, Issue 1, pp. 89–108, March 2004
  17. ^ Yeates, Lindsay Bertram (2004). Thought Experimentation: A Cognitive Approach (Thesis). p. 143.
  18. ^ Yeates, Lindsay Bertram (2004). Thought Experimentation: A Cognitive Approach (Thesis). p. 138-159.
  19. ^ Garbey, M., Joerger, G. & Furr, S. (2023), "Application of Digital Twin and Heuristic Computer Reasoning to Workflow Management: Gastroenterology Outpatient Centers Study", Journal of Surgery and Research, Vol.6, No.1, pp. 104–129.
  20. ^ Sanna, L.J., "Defensive Pessimism and Optimism: The Bitter-Sweet Influence of Mood on Performance and Prefactual and Counterfactual Thinking", Cognition and Emotion, Vol.12, No.5, (September 1998), pp. 635–665. (Sanna used the term prefactual to distinguish these sorts of thought experiment from both semifactuals and counterfactuals.)
  21. ^ See Yeates, Lindsay Bertram (2004). Thought Experimentation: A Cognitive Approach (Thesis). pp. 139–140, 141–142, 143.
  22. ^ a b c Also, see Garbey, Joerger & Furr (2023), pp. 112, 126.
  23. ^ a b Yeates, Lindsay Bertram (2004). Thought Experimentation: A Cognitive Approach (Thesis). p. 144.
  24. ^ a b Goodman, N., "The Problem of Counterfactual Conditionals", The Journal of Philosophy, Vol.44, No.5, (27 February 1947), pp. 113–128.
  25. ^ Chisholm, R.M., "The Contrary-to-Fact Conditional", Mind, Vol.55, No.220, (October 1946), pp. 289–307.
  26. ^ Roger Penrose (Shadows of the Mind: A Search for the Missing Science of Consciousness, Oxford University Press, (Oxford), 1994, p. 240) considers counterfactuals to be "things that might have happened, although they did not in fact happen".
  27. ^ In 1748, when defining causation, David Hume referred to a counterfactual case: "…we may define a cause to be an object, followed by another, and where all objects, similar to the first, are followed by objects similar to the second. Or in other words, where, if the first object had not been, the second never had existed …" (Hume, D. (Beauchamp, T.L., ed.), An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Oxford University Press, (Oxford), 1999, (7), p. 146.)
  28. ^ See Yeates, Lindsay Bertram (2004). Thought Experimentation: A Cognitive Approach (Thesis). pp. 139–140, 141–142, 143–144.
  29. ^ Goodman, N., "The Problem of Counterfactual Conditionals", The Journal of Philosophy, Vol.44, No.5, (27 February 1947), pp. 113–128; Brown, R, & Watling, J., "Counterfactual Conditionals", Mind, Vol.61, No.242, (April 1952), pp. 222–233; Parry, W.T., "Re?xamination of the Problem of Counterfactual Conditionals", The Journal of Philosophy, Vol.54, No.4, (14 February 1957), pp. 85–94; Cooley, J.C., "Professor Goodman's Fact, Fiction, & Forecast", The Journal of Philosophy, Vol.54, No.10, (9 May 1957), pp. 293–311; Goodman, N., "Parry on Counterfactuals", The Journal of Philosophy, Vol.54, No.14, (4 July 1957), pp. 442–445; Goodman, N., "Reply to an Adverse Ally", The Journal of Philosophy, Vol.54, No.17, (15 August 1957), pp. 531–535; Lewis, D., Counterfactuals, Basil Blackwell, (Oxford), 1973, etc.
  30. ^ Fillenbaum, S., "Information Amplified: Memory for Counterfactual Conditionals", Journal of Experimental Psychology, Vol.102, No.1, (January 1974), pp. 44–49; Crawford, M.T. & McCrea, S.M., "When Mutations meet Motivations: Attitude Biases in Counterfactual Thought", Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, Vol.40, No.1, (January 2004), pp. 65–74, etc.
  31. ^ Kahneman, D. & Tversky, A., "The Simulation Heuristic", pp. 201–208 in Kahneman, D., Slovic, P. & Tversky, A. (eds), Judgement Under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases, Cambridge University Press, (Cambridge), 1982; Sherman, S.J. & McConnell, A.R., "Dysfunctional Implications of Counterfactual Thinking: When Alternatives to reality Fail Us", pp. 199–231 in Roese, N.J. & Olson, J.M. (eds.), What Might Have Been: The Social Psychology of Counterfactual Thinking, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, (Mahwah), 1995;Nasco, S.A. & Marsh, K.L., "Gaining Control Through Counterfactual Thinking", Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, Vol.25, No.5, (May 1999), pp. 556–568; McCloy, R. & Byrne, R.M.J., "Counterfactual Thinking About Controllable Events", Memory and Cognition, Vol.28, No.6, (September 2000), pp. 1071–1078; Byrne, R.M.J., "Mental Models and Counterfactual Thoughts About What Might Have Been", Trends in Cognitive Sciences, Vol.6, No.10, (October 2002), pp. 426–431; Thompson, V.A. & Byrne, R.M.J., "Reasoning Counterfactually: Making Inferences About Things That Didn't Happen", Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, Vol.28, No.6, (November 2002), pp. 1154–1170, etc.
  32. ^ Greenberg, M. (ed.), The Way It Wasn't: Great Science Fiction Stories of Alternate History, Citadel Twilight, (New York), 1996; Dozois, G. & Schmidt, W. (eds.), Roads Not Taken: Tales of Alternative History, The Ballantine Publishing Group, (New York), 1998; Sylvan, D. & Majeski, S., "A Methodology for the Study of Historical Counterfactuals", International Studies Quarterly, Vol.42, No.1, (March 1998), pp. 79–108; Ferguson, N., (ed.), Virtual History: Alternatives and Counterfactuals, Basic Books, (New York), 1999; Cowley, R. (ed.), What If?: The World's Foremost Military Historians Imagine What Might have Been, Berkley Books, (New York), 2000; Cowley, R. (ed.), What If? 2: Eminent Historians Imagine What Might have Been, G.P. Putnam's Sons, (New York), 2001, etc.
  33. ^ Fearon, J.D., "Counterfactuals and Hypothesis Testing in Political Science", World Politics, Vol.43, No.2, (January 1991), pp. 169–195; Tetlock, P.E. & Belkin, A. (eds.), Counterfactual Thought Experiments in World Politics, Princeton University Press, (Princeton), 1996; Lebow, R.N., "What's so Different about a Counterfactual?", World Politics, Vol.52, No.4, (July 2000), pp. 550–585; Chwieroth, J.M., "Counterfactuals and the Study of the American Presidency", Presidential Studies Quarterly, Vol.32, No.2, (June 2002), pp. 293–327, etc.
  34. ^ Cowan, R. & Foray, R., "Evolutionary Economics and the Counterfactual Threat: On the Nature and Role of Counterfactual History as an Empirical Tool in Economics", Journal of Evolutionary Economics, Vol.12, No.5, (December 2002), pp. 539–562, etc.
  35. ^ Roese, N.J. & Olson, J.M. (eds.), What Might Have Been: The Social Psychology of Counterfactual Thinking, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, (Mahwah), 1995; Sanna, L.J., "Defensive Pessimism, Optimism, and Simulating Alternatives: Some Ups and Downs of Prefactual and Counterfactual Thinking", Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Vol.71, No.5, (November 1996), pp. 1020–1036; Roese, N.J., "Counterfactual Thinking", Psychological Bulletin, Vol.121, No.1, (January 1997), pp. 133–148; Sanna, L.J., "Defensive Pessimism and Optimism: The Bitter-Sweet Influence of Mood on Performance and Prefactual and Counterfactual Thinking", Cognition and Emotion, Vol.12, No.5, (September 1998), pp. 635–665; Sanna, L.J. & Turley-Ames, K.J., "Counterfactual Intensity", European Journal of Social Psychology, Vol.30, No.2, (March/April 2000), pp. 273–296; Sanna, L.J., Parks, C.D., Meier, S., Chang, E.C., Kassin, B.R., Lechter, J.L., Turley-Ames, K.J. & Miyake, T.M., "A Game of Inches: Spontaneous Use of Counterfactuals by Broadcasters During Major League Baseball Playoffs", Journal of Applied Social Psychology, Vol.33, No.3, (March 2003), pp. 455–475, etc.
  36. ^ Strassfeld, R.N., "If...: Counterfactuals in the Law", George Washington Law Review, Volume 60, No.2, (January 1992), pp. 339–416; Spellman, B.A. & Kincannon, A., "The Relation between Counterfactual ("but for") and Causal reasoning: Experimental Findings and Implications for Juror's Decisions", Law and Contemporary Problems, Vol.64, No.4, (Autumn 2001), pp. 241–264; Prentice, R.A. & Koehler, J.J., "A Normality Bias in Legal Decision Making", Cornell Law Review, Vol.88, No.3, (March 2003), pp. 583–650, etc.
  37. ^ Creyer, E.H. & Gürhan, Z., "Who's to Blame? Counterfactual Reasoning and the Assignment of Blame", Psychology and Marketing, Vol.14, No.3, (May 1997), pp. 209–307; Zeelenberg, M., van Dijk, W.W., van der Plight, J., Manstead, A.S.R., van Empelen, P., & Reinderman, D., "Emotional Reactions to the Outcomes of Decisions: The Role of Counterfactual Thought in the Experience of Regret and Disappointment", Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, Vol.75, No.2, (August 1998), pp. 117–141; Naquin, C.E. & Tynan, R.O., "The Team Halo Effect: Why Teams Are Not Blamed for Their Failures", Journal of Applied Psychology, Vol.88, No.2, (April 2003), pp. 332–340; Naquin, C.E., "The Agony of Opportunity in Negotiation: Number of Negotiable Issues, Counterfactual Thinking, and Feelings of Satisfaction", Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, Vol.91, No.1, (May 2003), pp. 97–107, etc.
  38. ^ Hetts, J.J., Boninger, D.S., Armor, D.A., Gleicher, F. & Nathanson, A., "The Influence of Anticipated Counterfactual Regret on Behavior", Psychology & Marketing, Vol.17, No.4, (April 2000), pp. 345–368; Landman, J. & Petty, R., ""It Could Have Been You": How States Exploit Counterfactual Thought to Market Lotteries", Psychology & Marketing, Vol.17, No.4, (April 2000), pp. 299–321; McGill, A.L., "Counterfactual Reasoning in Causal Judgements: Implications for Marketing", Psychology & Marketing, Vol.17, No.4, (April 2000), pp. 323–343; Roese, N.J., "Counterfactual Thinking and Marketing: Introduction to the Special Issue", Psychology & Marketing', Vol.17, No.4, (April 2000), pp. 277–280; Walchli, S.B. & Landman, J., "Effects of Counterfactual Thought on Postpurchase Consumer Affect", Psychology & Marketing, Vol.20, No.1, (January 2003), pp. 23–46, etc.
  39. ^ Randerson, J., "Fast action would have saved millions", New Scientist, Vol.176, No.2372, (7 December 2002), p. 19; Haydon, D.T., Chase-Topping, M., Shaw, D.J., Matthews, L., Friar, J.K., Wilesmith, J. & Woolhouse, M.E.J., "The Construction and Analysis of Epidemic Trees With Reference to the 2001 UK Foot-and-Mouth Outbreak", Proceedings of the Royal Society of London Series B: Biological Sciences, Vol.270, No.1511, (22 January 2003), pp. 121–127, etc.
  40. ^ Goodman's original concept has been subsequently developed and expanded by (a) Daniel Cohen (Cohen, D., "Semifactuals, Even-Ifs, and Sufficiency", International Logic Review, Vol.16, (1985), pp. 102–111), (b) Stephen Barker (Barker, S., "Even, Still and Counterfactuals", Linguistics and Philosophy, Vol.14, No.1, (February 1991), pp. 1–38; Barker, S., "Counterfactuals, Probabilistic Counterfactuals and Causation", Mind, Vol.108, No.431, (July 1999), pp. 427–469), and (c) Rachel McCloy and Ruth Byrne (McCloy, R. & Byrne, R.M.J., "Semifactual 'Even If' Thinking", Thinking and Reasoning, Vol.8, No.1, (February 2002), pp. 41–67).
  41. ^ See Yeates, Lindsay Bertram (2004). Thought Experimentation: A Cognitive Approach (Thesis). pp. 139–140, 141–142, 144.
  42. ^ a b Yeates, Lindsay Bertram (2004). Thought Experimentation: A Cognitive Approach (Thesis). p. 145.
  43. ^ a b See Yeates, Lindsay Bertram (2004). Thought Experimentation: A Cognitive Approach (Thesis). pp. 139–140, 141–142, 145.
  44. ^ a b c Also, see Garbey, Joerger & Furr (2023), pp. 112, 127.
  45. ^ Sarewitz, D. & Pielke, R., "Prediction in Science and Policy", Technology in Society, Vol.21, No.2, (April 1999), pp. 121–133.
  46. ^ Nowcasting (obviously based on forecasting) is also known as very-short-term forecasting; thus, also indicating a very-short-term, mid-range, and long-range forecasting continuum.
  47. ^ Browning, K.A. (ed.), Nowcasting, Academic Press, (London), 1982.
  48. ^ Murphy, and Brown – Murphy, A.H. & Brown, B.G., "Similarity and Analogical Reasoning: A Synthesis", pp. 3–15 in Browning, K.A. (ed.), Nowcasting, Academic Press, (London), 1982 – describe a large range of specific applications for meteorological nowcasting over a wide range of user demands:
    (1) Agriculture: (a) wind and precipitation forecasts for effective seeding and spraying from aircraft; (b) precipitation forecasts to minimize damage to seedlings; (c) minimum temperature, dewpoint, cloud cover, and wind speed forecasts to protect crops from frost; (d) maximum temperature forecasts to reduce adverse effects of high temperatures on crops and livestock; (e) humidity and cloud cover forecasts to prevent fungal disease crop losses; (f) hail forecasts to minimize damage to livestock and greenhouses; (g) precipitation, temperature, and dewpoint forecasts to avoid during- and after-harvest losses due to crops rotting in the field; (h) precipitation forecasts to minimize losses in drying raisins; and (i) humidity forecasts to reduce costs and losses resulting from poor conditions for drying tobacco.
    (2) Construction: (a) precipitation and wind speed forecasts to avoid damage to finished work (e.g. concrete) and minimize costs of protecting exposed surfaces, structures, and work sites; and (b) precipitation, wind speed, and high/low-temperature forecasts to schedule work in an efficient manner.
    (3) Energy: (a) temperature, humidity, wind, cloud, etc. forecasts to optimize procedures related to generation and distribution of electricity and gas; (b) forecasts of thunderstorms, strong winds, low temperatures, and freezing precipitation minimize damage to lines and equipment and to schedule repairs.
    (4) Transportation: (a) ceiling height and visibility, winds and turbulence, and surface ice and snow forecasts minimize risk, maximize efficiency in pre-flight and in-flight decisions and other adjustments to weather-related fluctuations in traffic; (b) forecasts of wind speed and direction, as well as severe weather and icing conditions along flight paths facilitate optimal airline route planning; (c) forecasts of snowfall, precipitation, and other storm-related events allow truckers, motorists, and public transportation systems to avoid damage to weather-sensitive goods, select optimum routes, prevent accidents, minimize delays, and maximize revenues under conditions of adverse weather.
    (5) Public Safety & General Public: (a) rain, snow, wind, and temperature forecasts assist the general public in planning activities such as commuting, recreation, and shopping; (b) forecasts of temperature/humidity extremes (or significant changes) alert hospitals, clinics, and the public to weather conditions that may seriously aggravate certain health-related illnesses; (c) forecasts related to potentially dangerous or damaging natural events (e.g., tornados, severe thunderstorms, severe winds, storm surges, avalanches, precipitation, floods) minimize loss of life and property damage; and (d) forecasts of snowstorms, surface icing, visibility, and other events (e.g. floods) enable highway maintenance and traffic control organizations to take appropriate actions to reduce risks of traffic accidents and protect roads from damage.
  49. ^ Yeates, Lindsay Bertram (2004). Thought Experimentation: A Cognitive Approach (Thesis). p. 146.
  50. ^ See Yeates, Lindsay Bertram (2004). Thought Experimentation: A Cognitive Approach (Thesis). pp. 139–140, 141–142, 146.
  51. ^ p. 24, Einhorn, H.J. & Hogarth, R.M., "Prediction, Diagnosis, and Causal Thinking in Forecasting", Journal of Forecasting, (January–March 1982), Vol.1, No.1, pp. 23–36.
  52. ^ "…We consider diagnostic inference to be based on causal thinking, although in doing diagnosis one has to mentally reverse the time order in which events were thought to have occurred (hence the term "backward inference"). On the other hand, predictions involve forward inference; i.e., one goes forward in time from present causes to future effects. However, it is important to recognize the dependence of forward inference/prediction on backward inference/diagnosis. In particular, it seems likely that success in predicting the future depends to a considerable degree on making sense of the past. Therefore, people are continually engaged in shifting between forward and backward inference in both making and evaluating forecasts. Indeed, this can be eloquently summarized by Kierkegaard's observation that 'Life can only be understood backward; but it must be lived forwards' …"(Einhorn & Hogarth, 1982, p. 24).
  53. ^ Yeates, Lindsay Bertram (2004). Thought Experimentation: A Cognitive Approach (Thesis). p. 147.
  54. ^ See Robinson, J.B., "Energy Backcasting: A Proposed Method of Policy Analysis", Energy Policy, Vol.10, No.4 (December 1982), pp. 337–345; Robinson, J.B., "Unlearning and Backcasting: Rethinking Some of the Questions We Ask About the Future", Technological Forecasting and Social Change, Vol.33, No.4, (July 1988), pp. 325–338; Robinson, J., "Future Subjunctive: Backcasting as Social Learning", Futures, Vol.35, No.8, (October 2003), pp. 839–856.
  55. ^ See Yeates, Lindsay Bertram (2004). Thought Experimentation: A Cognitive Approach (Thesis). pp. 139–140, 141–142, 146147.
  56. ^ Also, see Garbey, Joerger & Furr (2023), pp. 112, 127–128.
  57. ^ Robinson's backcasting approach is very similar to the anticipatory scenarios of Ducot and Lubben (Ducot, C. & Lubben, G.J., "A Typology for Scenarios", Futures, Vol.11, No.1, (February 1980), pp. 51–57), and Bunn and Salo (Bunn, D.W. & Salo, A.A., "Forecasting with scenarios", European Journal of Operational Research, Vol.68, No.3, (13 August 1993), pp. 291–303).
  58. ^ p. 814, Dreborg, K.H., "Essence of Backcasting", Futures, Vol.28, No.9, (November 1996), pp. 813–828.
  59. ^ Jansen, L., "Towards a Sustainable Future, en route with Technology", pp. 496–525 in Dutch Committee for Long-Term Environmental Policy (ed.), The Environment: Towards a Sustainable Future (Environment & Policy, Volume 1), Kluwer Academic Publishers, (Dortrecht), 1994.
  60. ^ Catholic Encyclopedia (1913)/Pandects "every logical rule of law is capable of illumination from the law of the Pandects."
  61. ^ Plato. Rep. vii, I–III, 514–518B.
  62. ^ Seyyed Hossein Nasr and Oliver Leaman (1996), History of Islamic Philosophy, p. 315, Routledge, ISBN 0-415-13159-6.
  63. ^ Yeates, 2004, pp. 138–143.
  64. ^ Jaynes, E.T. (1989).Clearing up the Mysteries, opening talk at the 8th International MAXENT Workshop, St John's College, Cambridge UK.
  65. ^ French, A.P., Taylor, E.F. (1979/1989). An Introduction to Quantum Physics, Van Nostrand Reinhold (International), London, ISBN 0-442-30770-5.
  66. ^ Wheeler, J.A, Zurek, W.H., editors (1983). Quantum Theory and Measurement, Princeton University Press, Princeton.
  67. ^ d'Espagnat, B. (2006). On Physics and Philosophy, Princeton University Press, Princeton, ISBN 978-0-691-11964-9
  68. ^ a b c Gualeni, Stefano (21 April 2022). "Philosophical Games". Encyclopedia of Ludic Terms. Retrieved 6 August 2024.
  69. ^ a b c Gualeni, Stefano (2015). Virtual Worlds as Philosophical Tools: How to Philosophize with a Digital Hammer. Basingstoke (UK): Palgrave MacMillan. ISBN 978-1-137-52178-1.
  70. ^ a b Gualeni, Stefano (2016). "Self-reflexive videogames: observations and corollaries on virtual worlds as philosophical artifacts". G a M e, the Italian Journal of Game Studies. 1, 5.
  71. ^ While the problem presented in this short story's scenario is not unique, it is extremely unusual. Most thought experiments are intentionally (or, even, sometimes unintentionally) skewed towards the inevitable production of a particular solution to the problem posed; and this happens because of the way that the problem and the scenario are framed in the first place. In the case of The Lady, or the Tiger?, the way that the story unfolds is so "end-neutral" that, at the finish, there is no "correct" solution to the problem. Therefore, all that one can do is to offer one's own innermost thoughts on how the account of human nature that has been presented might unfold – according to one's own experience of human nature – which is, obviously, the purpose of the entire exercise. The extent to which the story can provoke such an extremely wide range of (otherwise equipollent) predictions of the participants' subsequent behaviour is one of the reasons the story has been so popular over time.

Further reading

edit

Bibliography

edit
  • Adams, Scott, God's Debris: A Thought Experiment, Andrews McMeel Publishing, (USA), 2001
  • Browning, K.A. (ed.), Nowcasting, Academic Press, (London), 1982.
  • Buzzoni, M., Thought Experiment in the Natural Sciences, Koenigshausen+Neumann, Wuerzburg 2008
  • Cohen, Martin, "Wittgenstein's Beetle and Other Classic Thought Experiments", Blackwell (Oxford) 2005
  • Cohnitz, D., Gedankenexperimente in der Philosophie, Mentis Publ., (Paderborn, Germany), 2006.
  • Craik, K.J.W., The Nature of Explanation, Cambridge University Press, (Cambridge), 1943.
  • Cushing, J.T., Philosophical Concepts in Physics: The Historical Relation Between Philosophy and Scientific Theories, Cambridge University Press, (Cambridge), 1998.
  • DePaul, M. & Ramsey, W. (eds.), Rethinking Intuition: The Psychology of Intuition and Its Role in Philosophical Inquiry, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, (Lanham), 1998.
  • Gendler, T.S. & Hawthorne, J., Conceivability and Possibility, Oxford University Press, (Oxford), 2002.
  • Gendler, T.S., Thought Experiment: On the Powers and Limits of Imaginary Cases, Garland, (New York), 2000.
  • H?ggqvist, S., Thought Experiments in Philosophy, Almqvist & Wiksell International, (Stockholm), 1996.
  • Hanson, N.R., Patterns of Discovery: An Inquiry into the Conceptual Foundations of Science, Cambridge University Press, (Cambridge), 1962.
  • Harper, W.L., Stalnaker, R. & Pearce, G. (eds.), Ifs: Conditionals, Belief, Decision, Chance, and Time, D. Reidel Publishing Co., (Dordrecht), 1981.
  • Hesse, M.B., Models and Analogies in Science, Sheed and Ward, (London), 1963.
  • Holyoak, K.J. & Thagard, P., Mental Leaps: Analogy in Creative Thought, A Bradford Book, The MIT Press, (Cambridge), 1995.
  • Horowitz, T. & Massey, G.J. (eds.), Thought Experiments in Science and Philosophy, Rowman & Littlefield, (Savage), 1991.
  • Kahn, H., Thinking About the Unthinkable, Discus Books, (New York), 1971.
  • Kuhne, U., Die Methode des Gedankenexperiments, Suhrkamp Publ., (Frankfurt/M, Germany), 2005.
  • Leatherdale, W.H., The Role of Analogy, Model and Metaphor in Science, North-Holland Publishing Company, (Amsterdam), 1974.
  • ?rsted, Hans Christian (1997). Selected Scientific Works of Hans Christian ?rsted. Princeton. ISBN 978-0-691-04334-0.. Translated to English by Karen Jelved, Andrew D. Jackson, and Ole Knudsen, (translators 1997).
  • Roese, N.J. & Olson, J.M. (eds.), What Might Have Been: The Social Psychology of Counterfactual Thinking, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, (Mahwah), 1995.
  • Shanks, N. (ed.), Idealization IX: Idealization in Contemporary Physics (Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, Volume 63), Rodopi, (Amsterdam), 1998.
  • Shick, T. & Vaugn, L., Doing Philosophy: An Introduction through Thought Experiments (Second Edition), McGraw Hill, (New York), 2003.
  • Sorensen, R.A., Thought Experiments, Oxford University Press, (Oxford), 1992.
  • Tetlock, P.E. & Belkin, A. (eds.), Counterfactual Thought Experiments in World Politics, Princeton University Press, (Princeton), 1996.
  • Thomson, J.J. {Parent, W. (ed.)}, Rights, Restitution, and Risks: Essays in Moral Theory, Harvard University Press, (Cambridge), 1986.
  • Vosniadou, S. & Ortony. A. (eds.), Similarity and Analogical Reasoning, Cambridge University Press, (Cambridge), 1989.
  • Wilkes, K.V., Real People: Personal Identity without Thought Experiments, Oxford University Press, (Oxford), 1988.
  • Yeates, L.B., Thought Experimentation: A Cognitive Approach, Graduate Diploma in Arts (By Research) Dissertation, University of New South Wales, 2004.
edit
炖肉什么时候放盐 蚊虫叮咬红肿用什么药 gson是什么牌子 结核阳性是什么意思 异次元是什么意思
烹饪是什么意思 维生素b吃多了有什么副作用 什么车不能开 抗hcv是什么意思 戒指上的s925是什么意思
痛经吃什么止痛药 糖醋里脊是什么肉 人参什么时候吃最好 长期服用丙戊酸钠有什么副作用 咳嗽有白痰一直不好是什么原因
水土不服是什么意思 三叉神经疼吃什么药 复方药是什么意思 术后引流管什么时间可以拔 甲状腺肿大吃什么药
金酒是什么酒hcv8jop4ns9r.cn 脑子萎缩是什么原因造成的hcv8jop7ns3r.cn 肺部有阴影一般是什么病hcv9jop0ns2r.cn 为什么微信运动总是显示步数为0hcv7jop7ns3r.cn 地图鱼吃什么hcv9jop7ns0r.cn
低钾吃什么药hcv9jop5ns5r.cn 磨牙是什么原因引起的如何治疗hcv9jop7ns9r.cn 八月份是什么季节hkuteam.com dpd是什么意思hcv9jop4ns9r.cn 放疗期间吃什么食物最好hcv9jop4ns5r.cn
今年7岁属什么生肖hcv8jop7ns0r.cn 胸疼挂什么科室hcv8jop0ns3r.cn 老日念什么hcv8jop1ns0r.cn 为什么白带是黄色的hcv9jop4ns0r.cn 胃炎吃什么药最有效hcv9jop6ns9r.cn
玉婷是什么hcv8jop5ns6r.cn 农历六月初七是什么星座sscsqa.com 梦见鸡死了是什么预兆hcv9jop3ns0r.cn 煮肉放什么调料hcv8jop7ns6r.cn 房产证和土地证有什么区别hcv8jop6ns0r.cn
百度